Death, Life And The Question Of Identity Essay, Research Paper
Sam Vaknin’s Psychology, Philosophy, Economics and Foreign Affairs
Web SitesA classical point of departure in defining Death, seems to
be Life itself. Death is perceived either as a cessation of Life –
or as a “transit zone”, on the way to a continuation of Life by
other means.
While the former presents a disjunction, the latter is a continuum,
Death being nothing but a corridor into another plane of existence
(the hereafter).
Another, logically more rigorous approach, would be to ask “Who is
Dead” when Death occurs.
In other words, an identity of the Dying (=it which “commits”
Death) is essential in defining Death. But what are the means to
establish an unambiguous, unequivocal identity?
Is an identity established through the use of quantitative
parameters?
Is it dependent, for instance, upon the number of discrete units
which comprise the functioning whole?
If so, where is the level at which useful distinctions and
observations are replaced by useless scholastic mind-warps?
Example: if we study a human identity – should it be defined by the
number and organization of its limbs, its cells, its atoms?
The cells in a human body are replaced (with the exception of the
cells of the nervous system) every 5 years. Would this imply that
we gain a new identity each time this cycle is completed?
Adopting this course of thinking leads to absurd results:
When humans die, the replacement rate of their cells is infinitely
reduced. Does this mean that their identity is better and longer
preserved once dead? No one would agree with this. Death is
tantamount to a loss of identity – not to its preservation.
So, a qualitative yardstick is required.
We can start by asking will the identity change – if we change
someone’s’ brain by another’s? “He is not the same” – we say of
someone with a brain injury. If a partial alteration of the brain
causes such sea change (however partial) in the determinants of
identity – it seems safe to assume that a replacement of one’s
brain by another will result in a total change of identity, to the
point of its abolition and replacement by another.
If the brain is the locus of identity, we should be able to assert
that when (the cells of) all the other organs of the body are
replaced (with the exception of the brain) – the identity will
remain the same.
The human hardware (body) and software (the wiring of the brain)
are conversely analogous to a computer.
If we change all the software in a computer – it will still remain
the same (though more or less capable) computer. This is equivalent
to growing up in humans.
However, if we change the computer’s processor – it will no longer
be identified as the same computer.
This, partly, is the result of the separation between hardware
(=the microprocessor) and software (=the programmes that it
processes). There is no such separation in the human brain. These
1300 grams of yellowish material in our heads are both hardware and
software.
Still, the computer analogy seems to indicate that our identity
resides not in our learning, knowledge, or memories. It is an
epiphenomenon. It emerges when a certain level of hardware
complexity is attained. Yet, it is not so simple. If we were to
eliminate someone’s entire store of learning and memories (without
affecting his brain) – would he still be the same person (=would he
still retain the same identity)? Probably not.
Luckily, achieving the above – erasing one’s learning and memories
without affecting his brain – is impossible. In humans, learning
and memories ARE the brain. They change the hardware that processes
them in an irreversible manner.
This, naturally, cannot be said of a computer. There, the
separation is clear. Change a computer’s hardware and you changed
its identity. And computers are software – invariant.
We are, therefore, able to confidently conclude that the brain is
the sole determinant of identity, its seat and signifier. This is
because our brain IS both our processing hardware and our
processing software. It is also a repository of processed data. ANY
subsystem comprising these functions can be justly equated with the
system of which it is a part. This seems to hold true even under
the wildest gedankenexperiments.
A human brain detached from any body is still assumed to possess
identity. And a monkey implanted with a human brain will host the
identity of the former owner of the brain.
Around this seemingly faultless test revolved many of the debates
which characterized the first decade of the new discipline of
Artificial Intelligence (AI).
Turing’s Test pits invisible (hardware – less) intelligences
(=brains) against one another. The answers which they provide (by
teleprinter, hidden behind partitions) determine their identity
(human or not). When the software (=the answers) is accessible, no
direct observation of the hardware (=the brains) is necessary in
order to determine identity. But the brain’s status as THE
privileged identity system is such that even if no answers are
forthcoming from it – the identity will reside with it.
For instance, if for some logistical or technological problem, a
brain will be prevented from providing output, answers, and
interactions – we are likely to assume that it has the potential to
do so. Thus, in the case of an inactive brain, an identity will be
the derivative of its potential to interact (rather than of its
actual interaction).
After all, this, exactly, is what paleoanthropologists are
attempting to do. They are trying to delineate the identity of our
forefathers by studying their skulls and, by inference, their
brains and their mental potentials. True, they invest effort in
researching other types of bones. Ultimately, they hope to be able
to draw an accurate visual description of our ancestors. But we
must not confuse description with identity, phenomenology with
aetiology. What dies, therefore, is the brain and only the
brain.
Functionally, Death can also be defined (really, observed) from the
outside. It is the cessation of the exertion of influence (=power)
over physical systems. It is sudden absence of physical effects
exerted by the dead object, a singularity, a discontinuity. It is
not an inert state of things.
Inertia is a balance of forces – and in Death the absence of any
force whatsoever is postulated. Death is, therefore, also not an
entropic climax. Entropy is an isotropic, homogeneous distribution
of energy. Death is the absence of any and all energies. While,
outwardly, the two might seem identical – they are the two poles of
a dichotomy.
So, Death, as opposed to inertia or entropy, is not something that
modern physics is fully equipped to deal with. Physics, by
definition, deals with forces and measurable effects. It has
nothing to say about force-less, energy-devoid physical states.
Actually, this would be a stark contradiction in its terms.
Indeed, this definition of Death has reality itself to argue
against it.
If Death is the cessation of impacts on physical systems (=the
absence of physical effects), we are hard pressed to explain memory
away.
Memory is a physical effect (=electrochemical activity of the
brain) within a physical system (=the Brain). It can be preserved
and shipped across time and space in capsules called books or
articles (or art). These containers of triggers of physical effects
(in recipient brains) defy Death. The physical system which
produced the memory capsule will surely cease to exist – but it
will continue to physically impact other physical systems long
after its demise, long after it was supposed to have ceased to do
so.
Memory divorces Death from the physical world. As long as we (or
our products) are remembered – we continue to have a physical
effect on future physical systems. And as long as this happens – we
are not technically (or, at least, fully) dead. Our Death will be
fully accomplished only after our memory will have been wiped out
completely, not even having the potential of being reconstructed in
the future. Only then will we cease to have any dimension of
existence (=effect on other physical systems).
Philosophically, there is no difference between being influenced by
a direct discussion with Kant – and being influenced by his words
preserved in a time-space capsule (=a book). For the
listener/reader Kant is very much alive, more alive than many of
his neighbours whom he never met.
This issue can be further radicalized. What is the difference
between a two dimensional representation of Kant (portrait), a
three dimensional representation of the philosopher (a statute) and
yet another three dimensional representation of him (Kant himself
as perceived by his contemporaries who chanced to see him)?
As far as a bias-free observer is concerned (a camera linked to a
computer) – there is no difference. All these representations are
registered and mathematically represented in a processing unit so
as to allow for a functional, relatively isomorphic mapping. Still,
human observes will endow the three dimensional versions with a
privileged status.
Philosophically, there is no rigorous reason to do so.
It is conceivable that, in the future, we will be able to preserve
a three-dimensional likeness (a hologram), replete with smells,
temperature and tactile effects. Why should the flesh and blood
version be judged superior to such a likeness?
Physically, the choice of a different medium does not create a
hierarchy of representations, from better to worse. In other words,
the futuristic hologram should not be deemed inferior to the
classic, organic version as long as they both possess the same
information content.
Thus, the hierarchy cannot be derived from describing the state of
things.
An hierarchy is established by considering potentials, namely: the
future. Non-organic representations (hereinunder referred to as
“representations”) of intelligent and conscious organic originals
(hereinunder referred to as; “organic originals”) are finite. The
organic originals are infinite in their possibilities to create and
to procreate, to change themselves and their environment, to act
and be acted upon within ever more complex feedback loops.
The non-organic versions, the representations, are self contained
and final. The organic originals and their representations may
contain identical information in a given nano-second. But the
amount of information will increase in the organic version and
decrease in the non-organic one (due to the second Law of
Thermodynamics). This inevitable divergence is what endows the
organic original with its privileged status.
This property – of increasing the amount of information (=order)
through creation and procreation – characterizes not only the
organic originals but also anything that emanates from them. It
characterizes human works of art and science, for instance, or the
very memory of humans. All these tend to increase information
(indeed, they are, in themselves, information packets).
So, could we happily sum and say that the propagation and the
continuation of physical effects (through memory) is the
continuation of Life after Death? Life and Memory share an
important trait. They both have a negentropic (=order and
information increasing) impact on their surroundings. Does that
make them synonymous? Is Death only a transitory phase from one
form of Life (organic) to another (informational, spiritual)?
However tempting this equation is – in most likelihood, it is also
false.
The reason is that there are two sources of the increase in
information and what sets them apart is not trivial. As long as the
organic original lives, all creation depends upon it. After it
dies, the works that it has created and the memories that are
associated with it, continue to affect physical systems.
However, their ability to foster new creative work, new memories,
in short: their capacity to increase order through increased
information is totally dependent upon other, living, organic
originals. In the absence of all other organic originals, they will
stagnate and go through an entropic decrease of information and
order.
So, this is the crux of the distinction between Life and Death:
LIFE is the potential, possessed by organic originals, to create
(=to fight entropy by increasing information and order), using
their own software. Such software can be coded into hardware –
e.g., the DNA – and then the creative act involves the replication
of the organic original or parts thereof.
Upon the original’s DEATH, the potential to create is propagated
through Memory. Creative acts, works of art and science, other
creations can be carried out only within the software (=the brains)
of other, living, organic originals.
Both forms of creation can co-exist during the original’s life.
Death, however, is proclaimed only with the incapacitation of the
first form of creation (by an organic original independent of
others), only when the surrogate form of creation becomes
exclusive.
Memories created by one organic original resonate through the
brains of others. This generates information and provokes the
creative potential in recipient brains. Some of them do react by
creating and, thus, play host to the parasitic, invading memory,
infecting other members of the memory-space (=the cultural
space).
Death is, therefore, the assimilation of the products of an organic
original in a Collective. It is, indeed, the continuation of Life
but in a collective, rather than in an individualistic mode.
Alternatively, Death could be defined as a terminal change in the
state of the hardware with designated pieces of the software
injected to the brains of the Collective. This, of course, is
reminiscent of certain viral mechanisms. The comparison may be
superficial and misleading – or may open a new vista: the
individual as a cell in the large organism of humanity. Memory has
a role in this new form of social-political evolution which
superseded Biological Evolution, as an instrument of
adaptation.
Certain human reactions – e.g., opposition to change and religious
and ideological wars – can perhaps be viewed as immunological
reactions in this context.
Death Life And The Question Of Identity
65
0
8 минут
Темы:
Понравилась работу? Лайкни ее и оставь свой комментарий!
Для автора это очень важно, это стимулирует его на новое творчество!